symmetric monoidal (∞,1)-category of spectra
A ring is a principal ideal domain if
it is an integral domain (hence in particular a commutative ring)
every ideal in is a principal ideal.
Often pid is used as an abbreviation of “principal ideal domain”.
A pid can also be characterized as an integral domain wich possesses a Dedekind-Hasse norm, making very clear the fact that it is a generalization of an Euclidean domain.
any field
the ring of integers
a polynomial ring with coefficients in a field (in fact, for any commutative ring , the ring is a pid if and only if is a field)
a discrete valuation ring (for example, a ring of formal power series over a field)
any Euclidean domain
in the ring of entire holomorphic functions on every finitely generated ideal is principal (Helmer 40), but the ring is only a Bézout domain.
That both the integers and the polynomial rings over finite fields are principal integral domains with finite group of units is one aspect of the close similarity between the two that is the topic of the function field analogy. That also the holomorphic functions on the complex plane form a Bézout domain may then be viewed as part of the further similarity that relates the previous two to topics such as geometric Langlands duality. See at function field analogy – table for more on this.
In a pid , an element is irreducible iff is a maximal ideal.
Suppose is irreducible and . Then the ideal generated by is principal, say . Then and since is irreducible, one of is a unit; if is a unit then and thus , contradiction. So then must be a unit, i.e., is the improper ideal. Thus has no proper extension: is maximal.
For any ring , if is maximal and for a non-unit , then the inclusion is an equality by maximality, so for some . Then . In an integral domain we conclude ; thus is a unit.
A pid is a Noetherian ring.
The union of an ascending chain of ideals is an ideal ; if , then belongs to one of the , whereupon .
A PID is a unique factorization domain.
Working in classical logic, Proposition says that the reverse inclusion relation on the set of nonzero ideals is well-founded. Let be the subset of ideals that are products of finitely many (maybe zero!) maximal principal ideals. For any proper ideal , if every properly containing can be factored into maximals, then so can . (Spelling this out: either is maximal/irreducible, or factors as where both and are non-units; and factor into maximals by hypothesis, and therefore so does .) Thus is an inductive set, so by well-foundedness it contains every ideal , i.e., can be factored into irreducibles.
For uniqueness of the factorization, we first remark that if is irreducible and , then or . (For is a field and thus a fortiori an integral domain, so that if , then or .) Thus if are two factorizations into irreducibles of the same element, then divides one of the irreducibles , in which case and each is a unit times the other, meaning we can cancel on both sides and argue by induction.
If is a pid, then any submodule of a free module over is also free. (For the converse statement, see here.)
By freeness of , there exists an isomorphism , a coproduct of copies of (as a module over the ring ) indexed over a set , which we assume well-ordered using the axiom of choice. Define submodules of :
Any element of can be written uniquely as where and . Define a homomorphism
by . The kernel of is , and we have an exact sequence
where is a submodule (i.e., an ideal) of , hence generated by a single element . Let consist of those such that , and for , choose such that . We claim that forms a basis for .
First we prove linear independence of . Suppose , with . Applying , we get . Since , we have (since we are working over a domain). The assertion now follows by induction.
Now we prove that the generate . Assume otherwise, and let be the least such that some cannot be written as a linear combination of the , for . If , then , so that for some , but this contradicts minimality of . Therefore . Now, we have for some ; put . Clearly
and so . Thus for some . At the same time, cannot be written as a linear combination of the ; again, this contradicts minimality of . Thus the generate , as claimed.
Since the integers form a pid, and abelian groups are the same as -modules, we have
(Dedekind) A subgroup of a free abelian group is also free abelian.
The analog of this statement for possibly non-abelian groups is the Nielsen-Schreier theorem.
Also, since projective modules are retracts of free modules, we have
Projective modules over a pid are free. In particular, submodules of projective modules are projective.
(matrices over principal ideal domains equivalent to Smith normal form)
For a commutative ring which is a principal ideal domain, every matrix with entries in is matrix equivalent to a diagonal matrix filled up with zeros:
There exist invertible matrices and such that the product matrix is a diagonal matrix filled up with zeros:
such that, moreover, each divides .
For matrices with coefficients in the pid of integers see also
A finitely generated torsionfree module over a pid is free.
Let be a finite set of generators of , and let be a maximal subset of linearly independent elements. (Unless , then has at least one element, because is torsionfree.) We claim that can be embedded as a submodule of the free module generated by (which in turn is the span of as a submodule ). By Theorem , it follows that is free.
Let be the elements of . It follows from maximality of that for any , there is a linear relation
with . For each in the complement , pick such an , and form . Then the image of the scalar multiplication factors through , and is monic because is torsionfree. This completes the proof.
Let be a pid. Then an -module is torsionfree if and only if it is flat.
Suppose is flat. Let be the field of fractions of ; since is a domain, we have a monic -module map . By flatness, we have an induced monomorphism . For any nonzero , the naturality square
commutes, and since the map is multiplication by a non-zero scalar on a vector space, it follows that this map and therefore also is monic, i.e., is torsionfree.
In the other direction, suppose is torsionfree. Any module is the filtered colimit over the system of finitely generated submodules and inclusions between them; in this case all the finitely generated submodules of are torsion-free and hence free, by Proposition . Thus is a filtered colimit of free modules; it is therefore flat by a standard result proved here.
structure theorem for finitely generated modules over a principal ideal domain
In constructive mathematics, many important rings may fail to be principal ideal domains in the naïve sense; the notion of Bézout domain, in which only the finitely generated ideals are required to be principal, is better behaved.
For instance, the ring of integers is a principal ideal domain if and only if the law of excluded middle holds: In one direction, the usual proofs rely on being able to decide whether any particular integer belongs to the ideal or not. For the converse, let be an arbitrary proposition. Consider the ideal . By assumption, it is generated by some number . Since the integers are discrete, it holds that or . In the first case holds, in the second .
However, this ideal cannot be proved to be finitely generated either. If an ideal is generated by , then we may form their gcd one step at a time, which we can do algorithmically. Therefore, remains a Bézout domain.
On the other hand, we could try to modify the concept of principal ideal domain to recover a concept that is identical to the usual one in classical mathematics but also includes . For instance, we could demand that every decidable ideal is principal, or (potentially more strongly) that any ideal generated by a decidable subset is principal. While these seem to work at first, they are too weak to prove that every PID is a Bézout domain, so we should try to think of something better.
Some authors have tried to define a principal ideal domain as a Noetherian Bézout domain, but it is unknown if this still coincides in constructive mathematics with the definition of principal ideal domain above.
O. Helmer, Divisibility properties of integral functions, Duke Math. J. 6 (1940), 345-356.
Wikipedia, Principal ideal domain
Eric Wofsey, Principal Ideal Domains, (written for Mathcamp 2009) pdf
Henri Lombardi, Claude Quitté (2010): Commutative algebra: Constructive methods (Finite projective modules) Translated by Tania K. Roblo, Springer (2015) (doi:10.1007/978-94-017-9944-7, pdf)
Last revised on June 1, 2024 at 20:12:04. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.